Plamen Makariev
Sofia University
 
 

FRAMEWORKS FOR INTERCULTURAL UNDERSTANDING. ISLAM AS A CHALLENGE

This paper will not attempt to justify the need for intercultural understanding, an extensive subject which presumes a polemic on "two fronts" - against the liberalist thesis that public social life should be culturally neutral, but also against the radical communitarian position of antagonism to alien cultural presence. Here we will simply postulate the value of communication between cultural communities, and proceed to examine possible frameworks for intercultural understanding.
Mutual understanding becomes a problem when there is a clash of cultures that differ significantly. The level and substance of "cultural strangeness" vary greatly. There may be tensions in relations between cultural communities even if there is a low level of cultural difference - when the latter serves only as an occasion for the establishment of relations of the "in-group vs out-group" type. In such cases there are usually also other factors antagonizing the communities concerned. As an example, one can take the problems of the Hungarian minorities in Romania and Yugoslavia, or of the Catalan and Basque ethnic groups in Spain.
There is a cultural conflict proper when ethnic confrontation is combined with religious, or “civilizational” differences (Huntington, 96). Cases of the former type can be found both in modern societies and in societies where traditional custom prevails. The relations between Irish Catholics and Scottish Protestants in Northern Ireland are very typical in this respect, as are those between Muslims and Christians in Nigeria, or between Muslims and Hindus in India.
Interactions between communities, which are on different sides of the dividing line between modern and traditional types of culture, are even more problematic. This applies, for instance, to relations between the Western and the Islamic worlds. The cultural contrast between modern and traditional is a prime concern of disciplines such as intercultural communication, which deal mainly with the interaction between business partners from the US or Europe, on the one hand, and Asia or Latin America, on the other.
As regards the substance of the cultural difference examined in this paper, it may be delineated best against the background of the concept of culture from which we are proceeding. We will regard culture as a coherent set of standards of behavior and codes of "deciphering" meanings (see Carbaugh 90:7). Hence in discussing interactions between cultures, we are not concerned with relations between organized formations, such as states or political parties but, rather, with situations of harmony or confrontation between worldviews, attitudes, stereotypes. The "substance" of cultural conflict comprises the reactions of non-acceptance of what someone around you is doing that runs counter to your notions of proper or improper and, at that, he? is doing it not by chance or misunderstanding, but with all the self-confidence of a person following some unquestionable rules of conduct. We usually share such reactions with "our like" - with people who have been formed as individuals in the spirit of traditions identical to ours and who have shared views. Insofar as one of the main functions of culture is to ensure the predictability of actions and solidarity within the community (see Bohannan 95:50), the behavioral discord that emerges in cohabitation with cultural "otherness" could cause us considerable psychological discomfort.
Of course, a culture may tolerate a "foreign body" within its "fabric" painlessly if it has sufficiently powerful mechanisms of self-reproduction. In that case the "otherness" seems innocuous in any form whatsoever - as long as it abides by some universal rules of human cohabitation. It doesn’t matter if someone's dress or diet is peculiar, provided that the media, entertainment industry, educational institutions and public administration are constantly reasserting in countless ways one and the same invariable ideas of good and evil, of beautiful and ugly, of human dignity, honor, justice, etc. This creates the illusion of unproblematic multiculturality, which is typical of the self-awareness of modern societies and fosters the views of the relative insignificance of cultural differences.

The harmonization of interactions between cohabitant cultural communities presupposes dialogical relationships between them. If we use Habermas's term, their behavior towards each other ought to be of the communicative-action type, i.e. to be oriented towards mutual understanding (cf. Habermas, 90). Mutual recognition of validity claims is an important condition for the establishment of such a relationship. Particularly important in this regard are what Habermas defines as normative claims. Without respecting each other's normative claims, the parties cannot live together in harmony. Yet while those mutual claims can be harmonized through discourse in a culturally homogeneous environment - the methodology of this activity is expounded in detail by the so-called "discourse ethics" - interaction between different cultural communities seems quite problematic in this respect.
How can such a discourse proceed if the participants do not share a common life-world, if there are contradictions between their background moral values? To evaluate a validity claim, both the "hearer" and the "speaker" must have at least minimum intercultural competence with regard to one another. Otherwise the "speaker" will not know what to refer to in his argumentation, in order to make it acceptable to the "hearer”. And how could be decided, in cases of contradiction between normative validity claims, who ought to give way, i.e. to make a compromise with his interests in the name of ‘understanding” (“Verstaendigung”)? Each party might sincerely claim, that its interests are more substantially bound to the controversial normative matter. How can each of them judge whether the Other’s claim is right, provided that a judgment by analogy with one’s own attitude to this matter of practical discourse cannot be reliable, due to the cultural difference?

* * *
The problem of intercultural understanding may be studied from various aspects, applying the methods of cultural anthropology, social psychology, pedagogy, linguistics, literary theory, history, theology, philosophy, etc. A new, synthetic discipline has also been gaining ground in recent years: intercultural communication. Here we will confine ourselves to a philosophical case study: a study on the attempts of Islamic scholars to present the status of women in typical Muslim societies as morally justified in the eyes of the non-Muslim and, in particular, of the modern, Western world.
We believe that, notwithstanding the diversity in the treatment of this issue from an Islamic perspective (it is even difficult to talk of a single perspective that is exclusively representative of the entire Islamic world), several common features of the argumentation may be identified. A study of those features could help clarify the mechanisms of intercultural understanding as an element of intercultural communication.
Here we will consistently evaluate the positions at a meta-level only, i.e. we are concerned not with the truthfulness or acceptability of a given thesis, but only with the technique of its justification. Our critique will not focus on the content of the statements under consideration, however provocative some of them might sound to the average European or North American reader. Still, we hope that an elaboration of the mechanisms of intercultural understanding – which we are aiming at – would be instrumental against manipulative argumentation of positions, whose content is unacceptable to the general public.

This particular choice of case study (the attempts to justify - from an Islamic position - as understandable and morally acceptable to the surrounding world a controversial feature of Islamic culture) is also indicative of the methodology of our paper, albeit in another respect. We will not be dealing with the unilateral examination of an alien culture. No matter how well someone comes to know the respective culture's internal mechanisms of functioning, he would, at best, attain predictability of the respective community's behavior, levers for its manipulation. Yet this certainly does not mean understanding the culture as such.
Monological attempts to "understand" an alien culture could be an expression of an imperialistic, colonialist attitude - Edward Said offers a classical analysis of this position in “Orientalism” (cf. Said 95: 3-5), showing how in this particular case "understanding" may be manipulative to the point where reconstruction is substituted for knowledge of the subject. Monological "understanding" could also take the form of bona-fide misconception - as the manifestations of the Subject-centered Reason (Habermas 87:294) typical of Modernity. Either way, however, the alien culture is treated as an object that is unilaterally controllable by the subject, even if this is done with the best of intentions. The "Other" is not given the opportunity to speak of himself alone, to represent his own interests. He is denied maturity and autonomy that are equal to those of the subject. Apart from being unfair, such an approach to an alien culture is ineffective in establishing constructive intercultural relations. Without truly equal partnership, harmony in cohabitation is impossible.

In their overwhelming majority, the ideas about intercultural understanding follow the same pattern: presentation of the external, empirical differences as an effect of identical fundamental causes. Understanding the "Other" means to recognize "behind" his or her actions, (which might be incongruent with your ideas of proper and improper), the same cultural motives, which you follow yourself, but which are manifested in a different form.
From a social psychological perspective, R. Brislin examines intercultural understanding on a somewhat different plane. According to Brislin, the main purpose of this act is to achieve "isomorphism of the attributions" which the parties make concerning the same action of one of them. "This term refers to the ability to make the same attributions as the other person in the interaction" (Brislin 93:41). By "attribution" Brislin means the explanation attributed to a given action by the doer, insofar as s/he is aware why s/he is acting in this particular way, as well as by an outside observer (who might also be a recipient of the action in question). There is understanding only when those explanations are identical.
Since by rule a particular action is part of a continuous process of interaction, we usually have two parallel flows of attributions, which influence the real interaction and which are, even in the easiest intercultural relationship, only partly isomorphic. Indicatively, this concept of intercultural understanding presents the latter in its entire complexity.
It is very tempting to apply the pattern of "fundamental similarities - different empirical manifestations" to the value hierarchies that are at the core of moral orientation within different cultures. Arguably, the ultimate values are identical, or at least similar, across the world, but are merely interpreted and applied in a different way depending on the geographical and historical circumstances. In his book on religious tolerance Jay Newman, for example, coins the term "trans-cultural values," citing love, justice, peace, economic prosperity, wisdom, progress, self-realization, duty, honor (see Newman 82:66-67). Those values may be regarded as an ideal of what ought to be, and cultural differences, as an expression of different views on the ways of realizing the ideal.
This position may fit into the conceptual background of both cultural evolutionism and cultural relativism. The author quoted above tends to apply the former, insofar as he assumes that any society or religious group may be rated higher or lower by a "scale of civilization," depending on "how much or how successfully its ideal values have been realized" (Newman 82:68). As the quote shows, Newman assumes that the degrees of realization of one and the same ideal in different cases can be commensurable. Although two or more cultural communities may use alternative means towards one and the same end, it is possible to evaluate their progress at a given moment.
This relation between end and means, however, may also be interpreted in the spirit of cultural relativism. If one acknowledges the possibility that the alternative means towards an end might be radically incommensurable, the attempts to divide cultures into relatively advanced and relatively backward along the road to civilization would prove unjustified and even harmful, insofar as they fuel ambitions for the domination of some societies over others. If, for instance, we take human dignity as a common ideal in a modern and in a traditional value systems, we will see that the actual behavior that abides by this ideal is entirely different in the two cases. Respect for the dignity of the modern person is manifested foremost in the guarantee of his or her individual autonomy - inviolability of his or her private life, freedom of choice, responsibility in the light of universal norms of behavior?. A person's dignity in a traditional environment is, by contrast, measured mainly in the person's belonging to his community. Precisely the independence of an individual from particularistic interests, which is a condition for the realization of his or her dignity in Modernity, is counter-indicative for human dignity in traditional society. The closer someone's status is to the ideal of dignity in the one dimension, the further it is from the same ideal in the other dimension. In that case, how can one compare the progress made towards the end by either of the two means?
Yet irrespective of whether the scheme of the relation between cultural differences and similarities is applied in an evolutionist or relativist context, it works equally well. In both cases it is possible to achieve validation of normative claims - as long as the claims to tolerate cultural practices that contradict our beliefs are justified by means of values, which coincide with some of our own moral regulatives.
If our critique that, say, arranged marriages are incompatible with the human dignity of the young people involved, is countered by a simple reference to the respective ethnic community's traditions, this will not contribute to intercultural understanding. What moral binding power could alien cultural traditions have for us to make us accept a situation that runs counter to our criteria of socially acceptable behavior? Yet if, instead, we are offered arguments that show a culture-based difference in the very understanding of human dignity and justification of the thesis that in "that" cultural context this virtue is asserted precisely by the practice of arranged marriages, that will be a step towards mutual understanding.
Naturally, we are talking about cogent argumentation, not about declarative short-circuiting of the facts with the argued thesis. We should have the freedom to challenge each argument - in the case discussed above, we might very well fail to agree with the proffered justification of arranged marriages and remain firmly in opposition. Nevertheless, this would have been an attempt at intercultural communication.

How is the said scheme of validating normative claims applied by authors who are trying to "open up" Muslim culture, making it more understandable to the outside world? In the huge variety of positions and argumentative techniques, one can identify a selective approach to the universalistic justification of the specific features of the Muslim way of life: not everything in Islam can be and is worth defending.
The traditional way of legitimating scripture-based reforms of socio-cultural practices is by interpreting and reinterpreting scripture itself. If an author thinks that a particular practice ought to be changed, s/he tries to convince his or her readers that it is not directly prescribed by the word of God but ensues from the latter's misinterpretation or distortion by the interpreters. This reformist approach is manifested in one way or another in the development of any religion. Here, however, we will cite two not so trivial argumentations as a case of justifying changes in the Muslim way of life.
Zia Goekalp's approach to reforms in Islam is quite simple. He distinguishes two sources of the shari'ah: "one is scripture (nass) and the other - local practice, mores, custom or convention ('urf)" (Khuri 98:307). Only the divine element of shari'ah is sacred and not subject to change. The socio-cultural one is transitory and ought to be adjusted to the times and changing conditions.
The algorithm offered by another Islamic scholar, Fazlur Rahman, is more complicated. According to Rahman, the sacred text of the Qur'an has been offered to mortals in a concrete form, which corresponds to the specific historical conditions in Arab society in the age of the Qur'anic revelations. Were it not adapted to the needs and capacities of the people to whom it is addressed, the scripture would not have attained its divine purpose. Yet this means that one should distinguish between the principles enshrined in the Qur'an, which are sacred and eternal, and their concrete formulation, which is transitory and cannot be valid for other historical ages and peoples unless it is adapted accordingly.
The interpretation of the Qur'an must be updated by analogy. "The relationship between the eternal principles and Arabian life early in the seventh century (C.E.) must be precisely the same as that between the former and the various strands of Muslim life today" (Khuri 98:310). This means that the interpreter must have excellent knowledge of the situation during the original propagation of Islam and must be capable of, so to speak, back translation - from the empirically available text of the scripture back to its principles - in order to subsequently reproduce the relationship between those two levels with regard to the contemporary socio-cultural situation.

After an author has argued his or her thesis what in the Muslim way of life can get and warrants moral justification to the outside world, s/he faces the harder task: to present the cultural specificities in question as a realization of universal - to quote Jay Newman, "trans-cultural" - values. Contemporary studies usually focus on one or several historical factors which explain why the Muslim notion of a particular universal value differs from, say, the Western one. The practices which, to the outside observer, are in contradiction with a given value, are actually in harmony with the latter but - due to certain contingent historical circumstances - take a different form.
The traditional character of Muslim societies is cited as the primary factor in this respect. Indeed, from the perspective of Modernity it is easiest to understand cultural specificities that ensue from the difference between traditional and modern society, because one can proceed from the latter's own history. When European or North American readers study the Islamic mores, they cannot refrain from analogies with what they know about the not too distant past of their own civilization. If we abstain from the evolutionistic inclination to evaluate cultural specificities by level of development, to "rate" cultures as superior and inferior - in which case any similarity between someone's present and someone else's past suggest that the former is "lagging behind" the latter - the possibility of reasoning by analogy with our own history helps understand the other's specificity.
The category of "community" is particularly important in this respect. As is known, one of the main differences between traditional and modern societies is that relationships of what F. Toennies defined as Gemeinschaft prevail in the former, and of Gesellschaft in the latter (see Toennies 57). Then what could be so unusual and incomprehensible to us in the Muslim way of life, if the latter gives priority to a type of relationships which, albeit by now less significant, are still present in our social reality. Admittedly, the validity of universal values differs in content when seen from the "angle" of exclusivistic communal solidarity, but what could be wrong about those relationships from our point of view?
The traditional nature of Muslim societies contributes to their cultural specificity also with regard to the social role of religion. Islam is notorious for its claims to regulate every sphere of social life in depth, in minute detail - to maintain "a congruence of the fanum/sacred and profanum/profane sphere" (Trautner 99:I). Prima facie, this is a phenomenon all too familiar from the general history of religion, some sort of naive mysticism - an inability to distinguish between the natural and the supernatural - which attests to the primitive nature of communal mentality. This seems to be one of the "pains of growth" of any civilization from which society, in the course of its development and secularization, eventually breaks free.
Yet perhaps the vehement resistance which secularization encounters in the Muslim world and which creates the impression that the latter is, in a way, ultra-conservative, ought to be explained with, inter alia, a deeper cultural difference vis-a-vis the West. Let us remember that the general opposition between the material and the spiritual world is not self-evident, but dates back to Plato. Adopted by Christianity and asserted especially by St Augustine's De civitate Dei, it steers Western civilization towards development in the spirit of a dualistic, in this sense, worldview. Whereas Islam is characterized by a holistic view of being, which is too conceptualized by the theoreticians of this religion to be attributed to some sort of ignorance. Contemporary scholars, for instance, offer entirely articulate arguments in favor of the thesis that "it is not human reason that judges the status of the law [i.e. Of Muslim law, the shari'ah], but the law that directs the use of reason" (Khuri 98:302).? After all, today it is difficult to find firm believers in the absoluteness of Reason anyway. In postmodern discourse it is preferred to talk about a plurality of rationalities. In this context the claims on a society, in which Muslim law has the status of an immediate embodiment of the Divine Will, to conform its legislation to the standards of Reason, look like an attempt to impose on it an alien rationality.
Another factor that places the Muslim way of life in a rather different relation to universal values is that the Muslim countries are at a geopolitical disadvantage in regard to the West. Considering that the majority of these countries have been subject to colonial rule and that today all are the target of attempts at domination in one form or another, it is hardly surprising that a defensive position towards any modernization initiative is commonplace in Muslim societies. Such initiatives are often seen as a threat to the cultural identity of those peoples. This is due, inter alia, to the fact that so far most political regimes, which have committed themselves to modernizing reforms have followed a course of despotism and corruption, thus reasserting their subjects' conviction that modernization brings moral corruption.
All this has asserted a selective attitude to universal moral regulatives, with a preference for those that close, isolate the in-group from the rest of the world. A corporativistic morality, which applies the ethic standards of behavior differently to "us" and "them", is maintained. Consequently, Islam appears to be amoral or, at best, with a morality of its own, which is radically different from the universally acceptable, as a result of which people from the Muslim and those from the non-Muslim world are apparently not bound by any mutual moral commitments whatsoever.

So far we have discussed in principle a scheme of moral justification of the specificities of the Muslim way of life from the perspective of universal values. Let us now demonstrate how it is applied in practice. How facts are harmonized with values by correcting apparent incongruities through reference to the above-mentioned or other factors of their type. As noted at the beginning, this paper will focus on the issue of the status of women in Muslim societies - a problem that has sparked acute value-related conflicts between the West and the Muslim world.
The traditional rhetoric that justifies the underprivileged status of Muslim women in the public sphere lacks conviction for the outside observer. The opportunity of women to perform an important mission in the family, assigned to them by God - to keep the home as a "center of peace, civility, tranquility, and love, a safe haven and protection from the brutality of the outside world" (Haddad 98:5) - is cited as moral "compensation" for their isolation from public life. At that, women have an opportunity for full self-realization as individuals, because at home they can best realize their inborn feminine virtues, such as gentleness, compassion, intelligence, understanding. These virtues are invaluable in rearing children, but at the same time make women vulnerable in the outside world - a scene of conflicts and tensions, which require a masculine strength of character.
From the outside point of view, such considerations are cold comfort for the unequal status of women in public life. It turns out that women are incapable of coping with the big issues in life, and insofar as they might be useful in any way, that is to provide "logistical support" to men, to bring up their children and deal with the everyday issues of family life. By the scale of universal values, this type of human existence is hopelessly inferior.
That is the case, however, only if we ignore the special significance of the home and the family in the Islamic cultural context. Contemporary authors, who expound the Islamic position on the issue, conceptualize it with the help of a category that is universally comprehensible, insofar as it has been investigated in detail in international social sciences - on a sociological and socio-psychological, as well as philosophical plane. This is the category of "community."
As noted above, the role of the community in the Muslim way of life differs from that in the modern world. Richard Khuri characterizes this role by means of the category of "positive freedom." The latter implies a relationship between the group and its members, which binds, restricts, but also gives the individual a distinct identity - an identity without which the individual cannot be positively free. The Muslim community (which is called by Khuri "enabling community") has treated its members "as integral persons so that it is taken for granted that the Muslim must be able to express his whole being no matter how encompassing this may be, within the framework laid out by the community"? (Khuri 98:129).
While in contemporary Western society the boundaries between private and public life are, in general, also boundaries between spheres of community and Gesellschaft-type relationships, in the Muslim world the community has a tangible presence in the public sphere too. This civilizational specificity is used astutely by Islamic authors, who do not omit to stress that the Islamic family structure "is predicated by divine design as the paradigmatic social unit" (Haddad 98:19). In that case the woman's important role in the family also proves to be socially significant in general. Taking care of the "health" and viability of the family, building the character and value system of the young generation, the woman guarantees the cultural reproduction of society. In this context, the business activities of the man seem insignificant in their limitation and one-sidedness compared to the existential depth of the woman's mission. The fulfillment of this kind of tasks demands the woman's powerful individual presence in the community which, in its turn, is sufficient to justify the need of a high social status of women, as well as the prestige and self-confidence of a full-fledged member of society.
When discussing the justification of the important social role of women from an Islamic perspective, one should keep in mind that the arguments rule out gender rivalry in general. The leading position of men in both public life and family is not called into question even in the boldest variants of emancipatory discourse (see Haddad 98:20). The level at which women can seek self-realization is not that of competition among individuals. The female and male roles in community life are assumed to be mutually complementary with, however, the "power-related" actions of dramatic decision-making, taking responsibility for the fate of the community in the clash with external circumstances, wholly confined to the sphere of male competence.

How do all those considerations fit into the debate on the cultural specificities of the Muslim way of life which, from the Western perspective, are in contradiction with universal values? For lack of space we will not provide a representative picture of the clash of arguments in this sphere, but will confine ourselves to a concrete problem - that of the honor of women. This problem is a textbook case of a value conflict between civilizations. To the Westerner it is incomprehensible why a religion should impose a number of limitations on women's behavior, which are not self-evidently justified and, by rule, do not apply to men. This seems to be a typical case of injustice, of discrimination against women.
In traditional Islamic discourse, which does not take into account the opening up of Islamic culture to the world, the limitations in question are associated with familiar interpretations of scripture that present women as inferior to men, as particularly sinful, sensuous creatures - as temptresses by nature, incapable of controlling their lusts sufficiently. Those interpretations are called into question by many contemporary scholars (cf. Esposito/Haddad 98; Schoening-Kalender 97; Luckau 91; Brink/Mencher 97). Insofar as there are attempts to harmonize the status of women typical of Islam with moral regulatives respected elsewhere too, those attempts stress the specific role of the community in the Muslim world and, albeit to a lesser extent, of the cohesion of religion and morality, as well as the defensive position towards the global imposition of Western culture.
It is thus shown, for instance, that it is entirely wrong to approach the question of the honor of Muslim women by analogy with the situation in individualistic European or North American societies. In the latter women are as free as men to choose how they will behave. A woman’s decision in this respect binds none other than herself. For the Muslim extended family, however, the behavior of a woman who belongs to them is representative of their mores. An immoral, defamatory action would disgrace each of the other members of the community. This would be catastrophic for the community's prestige and would affect its status in society and, eo ipso, the future of all its members.
Considering that so much is at stake, shouldn't we approach with understanding the Muslim world's particular sensitivity to women's abidance by the moral norms? If a woman's dishonor would have such grave consequences and affect so many other people along with the woman herself,? isn't it justified for one and all to try to minimize the risk of women's disgrace? In this context, aren't the pedantic restrictions on women's behavior more acceptable from an outsider's point of view - restrictions that aim to rule out even the slightest element of sexual provocation on the part of women and that seem like a gross intervention in their private life. Yet if we assume that those restrictions are necessary, we must also acknowledge the right of anybody to watch over their application.
This brings us to a somewhat different understanding of certain cases of sexual aggression in Muslim countries, which look like gross disrespect for women's dignity - like actions whose express purpose is to humiliate women. This applies to sexual harassment in cases when, for instance, a woman is not dressed appropriately for the particular situation or when she appears in public without being escorted by a male relative if, by convention, she should have been. In such situations abuse may be seen as a sanction against socially undesirable behavior. This, of course, cannot justify aggression from the perspective of Modernity, but could nevertheless contribute to intercultural understanding.
Such an attitude to women takes an extreme form when sexual abuse is used as a weapon in a conflict between communities. One of the most brutal ways of humiliating a "hostile" community is to rape women, which belong to it. This is regarded as an extreme form of hostility virtually everywhere, but has special meaning and significance in an Islamic cultural context. There is sufficient evidence of clashes of this type between Muslim and non-Muslim communities too, e.g. in the conflicts in former Yugoslavia. At that, the Muslim population was usually the object rather than the agent of such aggression, which attests to a sort of "intercultural competence" of the other party.
Along with more intensive community life, the cultural specificities of the Muslim world are explained - in an effort to justify them in terms of universal values - by an emphasis on the holistic nature of Islamic morality. Unlike the European-type morality, where analytical distinctions are made and an internal differentiation is developed, in Islamic morality the ethic regulatives are in total unity with the religious ones and constitute, along with the latter, a monolithic set of rules of conduct. Hence the conservative and uncompromising nature of Islamic morality. "When a section of the moral edifice is allowed to be broken the whole structure weakens and gives in easily to pressure. And thus tolerance of an evil leads to other evils" (Abdul-Rauf 79:35). The author argues his thesis by referring to a scale of moral compromises typical of the Western world, which starts with apparently insignificant, harmless ones such as female public exposure and premarital love, and rises steadily, without crossing any visible boundary between acceptable and unacceptable, to such a moral absurdity as, according to Abdul-Rauf, uni-sex marriages (ibid.).
* * *
So far we have described a technique applied by some authors in their quest for moral justification of the specific features of the Muslim way of life to the "outside world." We have seen how those specific features are presented as realization of universal values, which, however, is determined by specific historical circumstances and therefore differs at the empirical level from the realization of the self-same values in other cultures with a different history. We have shown how those authors associate restrictions on women's behavior that appear absurd to the outside observer, with universal values such as honor, dignity, duty, solidarity, purpose of life, etc. Yet how convincing are such associations? Aren't they a superficial, propagandist construct? How could the success of such attempts to justify normative (in Habermas's terms) claims be evaluated in general?
The examples discussed above show that formal logic cannot be counted on in such cases - it is virtually impossible to strictly deduce cultural standards of behavior from universal values. Besides, we certainly cannot trust some sort of intuitive convincing power of the argumentation. The situation of intercultural communication itself greatly impedes an intuitive understanding of the Other's position and makes it difficult to establish what in this position is convincing and what isn't.
We mentioned at the beginning that Jay Newman presents cultural differences as an expression of different strategies of realization of the same ideals - of the so-called "trans-cultural values." This approach can arguably be applied to evaluate arguments of the type under consideration. One can compare the end (some universal value) and the means (alternative sets of cultural standards), and judge which means are adequate to the end, and to what extent. Newman cites cases of obvious incongruity between historical undertakings and the values in the name of which they have been allegedly launched. How could the attack on Poland in 1939 be adequate to Nazi declarations that the Third Reich was aspiring towards peace; or how could torture and burning on the stake be adequate to the Spanish Inquisition’s claims that it was guided by love for thy fellow (see Newman 82:70)?
Anyone with some knowledge about the history of the events cited by Newman ought to realize that it is possible to provide certain arguments that the means were indeed adequate to the end in both cases. It is a historical fact that Nazi Germany accused Poland itself of aggression and presented the attack as justified resistance. It is also known that by causing physical suffering to the heretics the Inquisition arguably helped them to atone for their sins and thus save their souls. One could always claim that under particular circumstances a given action or standard of behavior is in harmony with the universal regulative. In Newman's examples the means are so plainly inadequate to the ends only because of the historical distance from the events in question. If we take a closer look at the contemporary world, we will realize that it is far from easy to identify inadequacies similar to those cited above. Who could say for sure today, whether the Western military campaigns against Iraq or Yugoslavia were to the benefit of world peace, as claimed by the governments that waged them, or actually pursued entirely different goals.
Newman hopes that a mere "critical examination" (ibid.) is enough to distinguish adequate from inadequate means of realizing an ideal. This presumption seems rather optimistic. We believe that more powerful tools, e.g. publicity, ought to be used for the purpose. If anything can expose the demagogy of a claim that a particular cultural practice is in harmony with universal values, this is the free public clash of arguments "for" and "against." Of course, by publicity here we mean the discursive formation of the opinion and will of citizens (Habermas, 90), not the propaganda brainwashing machine used in totalitarian societies. Given certain conditions, which are formulated in their idealized form by Habermas in the book quoted above - rationality and "openness" of the process of communication, equality of participants, presence of a potential for self-transformation in communication - publicity ("Oeffentlichkeit") could be relied on to winnow just from unjust normative claims.
Yet this general possibility should not be taken for granted. Contemporary studies of publicity tend to overrate the homogeneity of the public sphere. The legitimating potential of public opinion drastically declines when the latter proves deeply divided in some respect. Even if, having taken our cue from Habermas and his idealizations, we ignore the possibilities for "faking" publicity, which ensue from the unequal distribution of the resources for participation in the public sphere, we should take into account the influence of cultural differences on the latter. Exclusion mechanisms are triggered almost automatically in regard to the representation of cultural "Otherness" in the public sphere. This is quite clear in the Western discourse concerning Islamic culture too. The latter has little if any possibility to represent itself in the Western public sphere. And this is not due only to lack of good will and material resources. There is also a deep mistrust and even suspicion of the normative claims of "the other side," an odd ring to its moral pathos, an apparent irrationality in the distribution of value priorities in the other culture.
How could one find a way out and use the otherwise huge legitimating potential of publicity to clarify the relation of the specific Islamic cultural practices and the universally accepted moral values. We think that a direct campaign against the heterogeneity of the public sphere has little chance of success. It would be more feasible to focus on intensifying and advancing in-group dialogical discourse. If the problem of "opening up" Islamic towards modern culture becomes a standing and significant issue of free discussion in the Muslim world, and this process is accompanied by an analogical development "on the other side," it will be possible to evaluate not the validity of the others' normative claims directly, with all their "intransparency," but the formal, procedural quality of the public discourse that has produced them.
To establish whether public opinion-making in another culture is fair - i.e. whether each person is free to uphold his or her position in a way that enjoys full respect, whether the end result of a debate on a given issue is the product of a reasonable exchange of arguments - you do not necessarily have to go into the specificities of the others' cultural life. In that case, if "the other side’s" in-group discourse meets the general formal criteria, you would be able to conclude that the normative claims formulated by this discourse really express the relation between the others' cultural practices and universal values, and are not yet another propaganda bluff. This will be a crucial step towards bringing empirical differences under the common denominator of fundamental similarities - which is the scheme of intercultural understanding promoted in this paper.
Of course, healthy skepticism demands consideration of the following question: isn't this approach to intercultural understanding yet another expression of cultural imperialism? Isn't this an attempt to impose a Western discursive procedure on Islamic culture? Will the Islamic position on any issue of interaction with other cultures be authentic if it is formulated by applying alien rules? Wouldn't it be legitimate to refuse to apply free and rational discourse to the elaboration of such a position simply because this procedure is against Islamic mores?
The fact that there are numerous publications on the problems of intercultural relations, which seriously and conscientiously promote the cultural "opening up" of the Islamic world "from within," suggests that in this particular case both sides have the will for meaningful and open dialogue. Admittedly, however, dialogue cannot start "from scratch" in principle. It is a higher form of interaction between cultures, which presumes the fulfillment of certain terms, the most important one of them being, it seems, that both parties should have attained at least a minimum level of cultural self-reflection.
 
 

REFERENCES

1979, Abdul-Rauf, Muhammad, The Islamic View of Women and the Family, New York, Robert Speller and Sons
1995, Bohannan, Paul, How Culture Works, New York, The Free Press
1997, Brink, Judy, Mencher, Joan, Mixed Blessings: Gender and Religious Fundamentalism Cross Culturally, London/New York, Routledge
1993, Brislin, Richard, Understanding Culture's Influence on Behavior, Fort Worth, Harcourt Brace College Publishers
1990, Carbaugh, Donal, Cultural Communication and Intercultural Contact, Hilsdale, N.J. Lawrence Erlbaum Associates
1990, Habermas, Juergen, Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action, Cambridge, Mass. MIT Press
1990, Habermas, Juergen, Strukturwandel der Oeffentlichkeit, Frankfurt/Main, Suhrkamp
1987, Habermas, Juergen, The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity, Cambridge, Polity Press
1998 Haddad, Ivonne Yazbeck, Islam and Gender. Dilemmas in the Changing Arab World, In: Esposito, John, Haddad, Ivonne (eds.) Islam, Gender and Social Change, Oxford. Oxford University Press
1996 Huntington, Samuel, The Clash of Civilizations and the Remaking of World Order, New York, Simon & Schuster
1998, Khuri, Richard, Freedom, Modernity and Islam, Syracuse, Syracuse University Press
1991, Luckau, Petra, Die Stellung der Frau in Islam, Bochum, Ruhr Universitaet
1982, Newman, Jay, Foundations of Religious Tolerance, Toronto, University of Toronto Press
1995, Said, Edward, Orientalism, London, Penguin Books
1997 Schoening-Kalender, Claudia, Feminismus, Islam, Nation, Frankfurt/Main, Campus Verlag
1999, Trautner, Bernhard, The Clash Within Civilizations: Islam and the Accommodation of Plurality, Bremen, Institute for Intercultural and International Studies
 
 


BACK TO RECENT PUBLICATIONS